He says that distributive justice is natural
justice and involves balancing shares with worth. In turn,
rectificatory justice involves straightening out by removing
unjust gain, restoring unjust losses, and other forms of
retribution for loss and/or damages. Reciprocity involves
the interchange of goods and services and does not coincide
with either distributive or corrective justice. Reciprocal
justice involves comparative advantages and is concerned
with particularized mutual benefits derived from
specialization of function.
In the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle states
that exchange depends on equality of both persons and
commodities. It is in this work that he concentrates on the
problem of commensurability. Aristotle used artisans as
examples for his general and abstract discussions found in
this work. In Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics he
deals with justice, is concerned with determining proper
shares in various relationships, analyzes the subjective
interactions between trading partners looking for mutual
benefit from commercial transactions, develops the concept
of mutual subjective utility as the basis of exchange, and
develops the concept of reciprocity in accordance with
proportion. In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle, in
his treatment of justice, applied the concepts of ratio and
proportion to explain just distribution.
Aristotle states that fair exchange is a type of
reciprocity, not of equality, but rather of proportion. This
is achieved by equalizing proportions of products. His
concern here is with the ratios in which goods are exchanged.
Individuals create products of different value and unequal
creators are made equal through the establishment of
proportionate equality between the products. This led
Aristotle to the consideration of commensurability and to
inquire into the notion of exchange values.
According to Aristotle, value is assigned by man
and is not inherent in the goods themselves. He says that
exchange occurs because what the participants want is
different from what they have to offer. Need plus demand is
what goes into determining proportionate reciprocity in a
given situation. Aristotle explains that the parties form
their own estimations, bargain in the market, and make their
own terms and exchange ratios. The exchange ratio is simply
the price of things. For Aristotle, voluntary is presumed
just. Exchange must be mutually satisfactory. He sees
mutuality as the basis for exchange and the equating of
subjective utilities as the precondition of exchange. There
is a range of reciprocal mutuality that brings about
exchange. The actual particular price is determined by
bargaining between the two parties who are equal as persons
and different only with respect to their products.
Aristotle appears to have recognized the
subjective and relational nature of an exchange ratio. He
observed that an exchange ratio is not a ratio of goods
alone nor merely a ratio of people exchanging the goods
involved in the transaction. Rather, it is simultaneously a
ratio reflecting the interrelationships among and between
all of the people and all of the goods involved in this
transaction. This ratio of proportionate reciprocity is used
to equalize both goods and persons.
For Aristotle, money is a medium of exchange that
makes exchange easier by translating subjective qualitative
phenomena into objective quantitative phenomena. Although
subjective psychological want satisfaction cannot be
directly measured, the approximate extent of want
satisfaction can be articulated indirectly through money.
Not only does money eliminate the need for a double
coincidence of wants, it also supplies a convenient and
acceptable expression for the exchange ratio between various
goods. Money, as an intermediate measure of all things, is
able to express reciprocity in accordance with a proportion
and not on the basis of a precisely equal ratio. Money,
according to Aristotle, has become a convention or type of
representation, by which all goods can be measured by some
one thing. Money, as a modulating element and representation
of demand, becomes a useful common terminological tool in
the legal stage of the bargaining process.
The Household and the Polis |
In the Politics,
Aristotle discusses exchange, barter, retail trade, and
usury. He explains that exchange takes place because of
natural needs and the fact that some people have more of a
good and some have less of it. He says that natural exchange
redistributes goods to supply deficiencies out of surpluses.
Voluntary exchange occurs between self-sufficient citizens
who exchange surpluses, which they value less, for their
neighbor's surpluses, which they value more.
For Aristotle, true wealth is the available stock
of useful things (i.e., use values). He is concerned with
having enough useful things to maintain the needs of the
household and the polis. He says that wealth-getting
that aims at use-value is legitimate. Use-value or true
value involves goods that are necessary for life and for the
household or the community of the city. Aristotle considers
both the household and the polis to be natural forms
of association. It is not against nature when individual
households mutually exchange surpluses to satisfy the
natural requirement of self-sufficiency. Aristotle considers
friendship to be a necessary condition for natural exchange.
Aristotle maintains that property must be used in
a way that is compatible with its nature. Its use must
benefit the owner by also being a necessary means of his
acting in correspondence with his own nature. In the
Politics, Aristotle distinguishes between natural and
unnatural acquisition and discusses the problem of excess
property. He says that the right to property is limited to
what is sufficient to sustain the household and the polis
life of the city. He explains that exchange between
households requires mutual judgments of equal participants
in the life of the polis. The life of the household
is a sound and productive means to polis life if it
produces only the necessary goods and services that provide
a setting for the exercise and development of the
potentialities required for polis life.
Aristotle emphasizes the importance of natural
limits in a system of natural relationships. He says that
natural exchange has a natural end when the item needed is
acquired. Production is the natural process of obtaining
things for life's needs. Aristotle maintains that there is a
limit to the amount of property that can be justifiably
acquired as well as a limit to the ways in which it can be
legitimately acquired.
According to Aristotle, a household relies on
exchange to supply property necessary to the household so
that the citizen can develop his humanity. Natural exchange
operates within an environment of friendship and mutual
concern to complement the basic self-sufficiency of the
household. Natural exchange between households requires the
exercise of virtues and furnishes a bridge between one's
work and well-being. A wide range of material goods is
needed to attain a person's moral excellence. Economic
activity is necessary to permit leisure and the material
instruments necessary for a person to develop the full range
of his potential and thereby flourish. Aristotle teaches
that eudaimonia involves the total spectrum of moral
and intellectual excellences.
Aristotle explains that wealth derives its value
from its contribution to the acquisition of other goods
desirable for their own sake. Wealth and external or
exterior goods are instruments that facilitate virtuous
activity and eudaimonia, are means to an end, and
have some natural limit with respect to each individual.
Aristotle says that the polis exists for
the sake of the good life, that the polis is a
partnership in living well, and that mutual interaction is
the bond that holds society together. He observed that
people are related to each other through the medium of goods
but that acquisition beyond the necessary diverts the
citizen's capacities from the sphere of polis life.
Advocating an inclusive-end teleology, Aristotle endorsed an
active life devoted to a wide range of intellectual and
moral perfections including the active engagement in civic
affairs.
In the Politics, Aristotle advanced the
synergistic idea of social aggregation with the aggregate
benefits to people exceeding the objective total of the
benefits to individuals qua individuals. He sees this
excess amount of benefits as a positive measurement of the
goodwill created through association and as a reflection of
the unifying strength of a society. In part, it is the
mutual benefits of exchange which bring people together with
one desiring another's goods more than he desires his own
and vice versa.
In the Politics,
Aristotle delineates the historical development of money
from its initial existence as a commodity. He also discusses
the entire range of commodity exchange including barter,
retail trade, and usury.
Aristotle declares that the first type of exchange,
barter, the direct non-monetary exchange of commodities, is
natural because it satisfies the natural requirement of
sufficiency. After direct working of the land, barter
between households is the next most natural means of wealth
acquisition. For Aristotle, natural exchange is based on the
right to property being determined by the capacity for its
proper use. He sees barter as natural but inadequate because
of the difficulty of matching households with complementary
surpluses and deficiencies. The concepts of surplus and
deficiency are normative and derive from the right of
property.
Aristotle is irresolute and ambivalent regarding
the second form of exchange which involves the transferring
of goods between households but mediated by money. Here each
participant starts and ends with use value which he approves
of but the item is not being used in its natural aim or
function because it was not made to be exchanged. Aristotle
observes that what is natural is better than what is
acquired and that an item that is final is superior to
another thing that is wanted for the sake of this item.
The introduction of money eliminates the problem
of the double coincidence of wants. For Aristotle, the
legitimate end of money is as a medium of exchange but not
as wealth or as a store of value. He observed that money
became the representation of want by agreement on law. A
currency acceptable within the polis permits the full
potential to be realized.
Aristotle thought that money departs from its
natural function as a medium of exchange when it becomes the
beginning and end of exchange with no limit to the end it
seeks. The ease of exchange permitted by the use of money
makes it possible to engage in large production projects for
exchange purposes instead of for direct household use. This
can corrupt natural exchange for which money is a valuable
instrument. Money, rather than serving simply to facilitate
commodity exchange, can become the goal and end in itself.
In the third form of exchange, retail trade, a
person buys in order to sell at a profit. Retail trade is
concerned with getting a sum of money rather than acquiring
something that is needed and therefore consumed. Whereas
Aristotle views household management as praiseworthy and as
having a natural terminus, he is skeptical about retail
trade because it has no natural terminus and is only
concerned with getting a sum of money. Retail trade knows no
limits. When money becomes an intermediate element in
exchange, the natural limits on physical wants no longer
exercise restraints on a person's desires. The lack of
effective natural restraints leads to the unlimited desire
for wealth. There exist no natural conditions restricting a
person's desire to acquire money wealth.
For Aristotle, retail trade is not a way of
attaining true wealth because its goal is a quantity of
money. He criticizes money-making as a way of gaining wealth.
The end of retail trade is not true wealth but wealth as
exchange value in the form of a sum of money. Aristotle
observes that exchange value is essentially a quantitative
matter that has no limit of its own. He says that it is from
the existence of wealth as exchange value that we derive the
idea that wealth is unlimited.
In Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics,
Aristotle states that commodity exchange between craftsmen
is a natural but inferior form of exchange that is not
closely connected to polis life. He says that
craftsmen are involved with specialized production based on
unlimited and unnatural acquisition, are not the equals of
household heads, and are therefore unsuited for citizenship
and for polis life.
The fourth form of trade is usury – the begetting
of money from money. Aristotle says that the usurer is the
most unnatural of all practitioners of the art of
money-making. The lending of money at interest is condemned
as the most unnatural mode of acquisition. Aristotle
insisted that money was barren. He did not comprehend that
interest was payment for the productive use of resources
made available by another person.
Aristotle's economic criticisms are directed at
wealth-getting in the sense of money-making. He disregards
the fact that men were able to search for unlimited wealth
even before money came into existence. Although he realized
that wanting too much is a human failing, he placed a great
deal of blame on money because it had no natural terminus.
Aristotle taught that when a man pursues wealth in the form
of exchange value he would undermine the proper and moral
use of his human capacities. He fails to mention that men of
commerce provide useful public service and make money only
if they do so.
An Originator of Economic Analysis |
Aristotle saw so much even in
the field of economics. He foresaw significant elements of
Austrian value theory. For example, he glimpsed the concept
of diminishing utility and its application to exchange value
(i.e., price) determination. He held a theory of the
importance of value determination in evaluating the
efficiency of means in attaining human objectives. He also
anticipated the Austrian theory of imputation that holds
that the value of productive factors can be obtained via
imputation from the market values of final products.
Aristotle was the first to draw a distinction between value
in use and exchange value. His pre-marginal utility theory
also rejected the labor theory of value that later was held
by many of the classical economists. In addition, he was the
first thinker to analyze the problem of commensurability.
Additionally, Aristotle recognized the paradox of value and
the operation of the principle of scarcity. Although
Aristotle's economic insights and influence on the
development of economic thought were considerable, he did
make some errors and failed to fully appreciate that markets
and money-making activities could provide a mechanism
through which order in society could be produced through
individuals pursuing their own ends. Nevertheless, Aristotle
is one of the great thinkers in the history of economic
thought.
|